Mentalism (psychology)
In psychology, mentalism refers to those branches of study that concentrate on perception and thought processes: for example, mental imagery, consciousness and cognition, as in cognitive psychology. The term mentalism has been used primarily by behaviorists who believe that scientific psychology should focus on the structure of causal relationships to conditioned and operant responses[1] or on the functions of behavior.[2]
Neither mentalism nor behaviorism are mutually exclusive fields; elements of one can be seen in the other, perhaps more so in modern times compared to the advent of psychology over a century ago.[1]:11–12, 184[3]
Classical mentalism
Psychologist Allan Paivio used the term classical mentalism to refer to the introspective psychologies of Edward Titchener and William James.[3]:263 Despite Titchener being concerned with structure and James with function, both agreed that consciousness was the subject matter of psychology, making psychology an inherently subjective field.[3]:263
The rise of behaviorism
Concurrently thriving alongside mentalism since the inception of psychology was the functional perspective of behaviorism. However, it was not until 1913, when psychologist John B. Watson published his article "Psychology as the Behaviorist Views It" that behaviorism began to have a dominant influence.[4][3]:267 Watson's ideas sparked what some have called a paradigm shift in American psychology,[5] emphasizing the objective and experimental study of human behavior, rather than subjective, introspective study of human consciousness. Behaviorists considered that the study of consciousness was impossible to do, or unnecessary, and that the focus on it to that point had only been a hindrance to the field reaching its full potential.[4][3]:267–268 For a time, behaviorism would go on to be a dominant force driving psychological research, advanced by the work of luminaries such as Ivan Pavlov, Edward Thorndike, Watson, and especially B.F. Skinner.[6]:30
The new mentalism
A scathing review of B.F. Skinner's book Verbal Behavior by Noam Chomsky in 1959 heralded a shift back to a focus on the mental in psychology with the beginning of the cognitive revolution.[7] Critical to the successful revival of the mind or consciousness as a primary focus of study in psychology (and in related fields such as cognitive neuroscience) were technological and methodological advances, which eventually allowed for brain mapping, among other new techniques.[8] These advances provided an objectively experimental way to begin to study perception and consciousness, effectively nullifying the main criticism of mentalism half a century earlier.[8]
However, the cognitive revolution did not kill behaviorism as a research program; in fact, research on operant conditioning actually grew at a rapid pace during the cognitive revolution.[1] In 1994, scholar Terry L. Smith surveyed the history of radical behaviorism and concluded that "even though radical behaviorism may have been a failure, the operant program of research has been a success. Furthermore, operant psychology and cognitive psychology complement one another, each having its own domain within which it contributes something valuable to, but beyond the reach of, the other."[1]:xii
See also
- Cartesianism
- Cognitivism (psychology)
- Property dualism
- Dualism (philosophy of mind)
References
- Smith, Terry L. (1994). Behavior and its causes: philosophical foundations of operant psychology. Studies in cognitive systems. 16. Dordrecht; Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-8102-8. ISBN 0792328159. OCLC 30158598.
- Carr, Edward G. (Spring 1993). "Behavior analysis is not ultimately about behavior". The Behavior Analyst. 16 (1): 47–49. doi:10.1007/bf03392608. PMC 2733570. PMID 22478131.
The stimulus-response (S-R) psychology of Watson (1913) is ultimately about behavior and is definitely mechanistic. The behavior-analytic approach of Skinner (1938, 1953) is not ultimately about behavior, and it is definitely not mechanistic. As operant psychologists, we are not concerned with identifying stimuli and responses that bear some fixed relationship to one another and that can be used as building blocks to explain complex behavior patterns. As operant psychologists, we are concerned, first and foremost, with the functions of behavior or, in lay terms, with purpose (Lee, 1988; Morris, 1993; Skinner, 1974), even though we do not analyze and use the term purpose as a lay person would. [...] Functionalism would have been a better term for what we are about but, unfortunately, that term has already been used to describe a school of psychology quite different from ours.
- Paivio, Allan (1975). "Neomentalism". Canadian Journal of Psychology. 29 (4): 263–291. doi:10.1037/h0082031.
- Watson, John B. (1913). "Psychology as the behaviorist views it". Psychological Review. 20 (2): 158–177. doi:10.1037/h0074428.
- Leahey, Thomas H. (February 1992). "The mythical revolutions of American psychology". American Psychologist. 47 (2): 308–318. doi:10.1037/0003-066X.47.2.308.
- O'Donohue, William T.; Ferguson, Kyle E. (2001). The psychology of B.F. Skinner. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. ISBN 0761917586. OCLC 45188938.
- Trask, Robert Lawrence (2007). "Behaviorism". Language and linguistics: the key concepts. Routledge key guides (2nd ed.). Abingdon; New York: Routledge. pp. 30–31. ISBN 9780415413596. OCLC 75087994.
- Dehaene, Stanislas (2014). Consciousness and the brain: deciphering how the brain codes our thoughts. New York: Viking. p. 43. ISBN 9780670025435. OCLC 849719164.
In that sense, the behaviorists were right: as a method, introspection provides a shaky ground for a science of psychology, because no amount of introspection will tell us how the mind works. However, as a measure, introspection still constitutes the perfect, indeed the only, platform on which to build a science of consciousness, because it supplies a crucial half of the equation—namely, how subjects feel about some experience (however wrong they are about the ground truth). To attain a scientific understanding of consciousness, we cognitive neuroscientists "just" have to determine the other half of the equation: Which objective neurobiological events systematically underlie a person's subjective experience?
Further reading
- Burgos, José E.; Killeen, Peter R. (June 2019). "Suing for peace in the war against mentalism". Perspectives on Behavior Science. 42 (2): 241–266. doi:10.1007/s40614-018-0169-2. PMC 6701732.CS1 maint: ref=harv (link)
- Burgos, José E. (2016). "Antidualism and antimentalism in radical behaviorism" (PDF). Behavior & Philosophy. 43: 1–37. See also the six responses to Burgos in volume 44 of Behavior & Philosophy.
- Lo Dico, Giuseppe (2016). Philosophical and empirical approaches to psychology: mentalism vs. antimentalism. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books. ISBN 9781498516600. OCLC 922913669.CS1 maint: ref=harv (link)
- Turner, Robert (March 2012). "The need for systematic ethnopsychology: the ontological status of mentalistic terminology". Anthropological Theory. 12 (1): 29–42. doi:10.1177/1463499612436462.CS1 maint: ref=harv (link)
- Charles, Eric P. (September 2011). "Seeing minds in behavior: descriptive mentalism". Review of General Psychology. 15 (3): 267–276. doi:10.1037/a0024870.CS1 maint: ref=harv (link)
- Carlson, Richard A. (June 2002). "Mentalism, information, and consciousness". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 25 (3): 333. doi:10.1017/S0140525X02250062.CS1 maint: ref=harv (link)
- Hocutt, Max (1996). "Behaviorism as opposition to Cartesianism". In O'Donohue, William T.; Kitchener, Richard F. (eds.). The philosophy of psychology. London; Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. pp. 81–95. ISBN 0761953043. OCLC 41663265.CS1 maint: ref=harv (link)
- Preston, Beth (August 1994). "Behaviorism and mentalism: Is there a third alternative?". Synthese. 100 (2): 167–196. doi:10.1007/BF01063809. JSTOR 20117925.CS1 maint: ref=harv (link)
- Moore, Jay (1989). "Why methodological behaviorism is mentalistic". Theoretical & Philosophical Psychology. 9 (2): 20–27. doi:10.1037/h0091470.CS1 maint: ref=harv (link)
- Bunge, Mario; Ardila, Rubén (1987). "Brainless psychology: mentalism and behaviorism". Philosophy of psychology. New York: Springer-Verlag. pp. 87–135. doi:10.1007/978-1-4612-4696-1. ISBN 0387964428. OCLC 14414028.CS1 maint: ref=harv (link)
- Schnaitter, Roger (1986). "A coordination of differences: behaviorism, mentalism and the foundation of psychology". In Knapp, Terry J.; Robertson, Lynn C. (eds.). Approaches to cognition: contrasts and controversies. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. pp. 291–315. ISBN 0898596238. OCLC 12556673.CS1 maint: ref=harv (link)
- Sober, Elliott (1983). "Mentalism and behaviorism in comparative psychology". In Rajecki, D. W. (ed.). Comparing behavior: studying man studying animals. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. pp. 113–142. ISBN 0898592593. OCLC 9255523.CS1 maint: ref=harv (link)