Jus ad bellum

Jus ad bellum (/js/ YOOS or /ʌs/ in the traditional English pronunciation of Latin; Latin for "right to war") is a set of criteria that are to be consulted before engaging in war in order to determine whether entering into war is permissible, that is, whether it is a just war.

Definition

Jus ad bellum is sometimes considered a part of the laws of war, but the term "laws of war" can also be considered to refer to jus in bello, which concerns whether a war is conducted justly (regardless of whether the initiation of hostilities was just). "Jus ad bellum refers to the conditions under which States may resort to war or to the use of armed force in general."[1] These rules focus on certain criteria for what makes a war just.

Article 51 of the UN Charter clarifies: "Nothing in the present Charter shall impair the inherent right of individual or collective self-defense if an armed attack occurs against a Member of the United Nations."[2]

An international agreement limiting the justifiable reasons for a country to declare war against another is concerned with jus ad bellum. In addition to bilateral non-aggression pacts, the twentieth century saw multilateral treaties defining entirely new restrictions against going to war. The three most notable examples are the Kellogg-Briand Pact outlawing war as an instrument of national policy, the London Charter (known also as the Nuremberg Charter) defining "crimes against peace" as one of three major categories of international crime to be prosecuted after World War II, and the United Nations Charter, which binds nations to seek resolution of disputes by peaceful means and requires authorization by the United Nations before a nation may initiate any use of force against another, beyond the inherent right of self-defense against an armed attack.[2]

By contrast, agreements defining limits on acceptable conduct while already engaged in war are considered "rules of war" and are referred to as the jus in bello. Thus, the Geneva Conventions are a set of "jus in bello". Doctrines concerning the protection of civilians in wartime, or the need for "proportionality" when force is used, are addressed to issues of conduct within a war, but the same doctrines can also shed light on the question of when it is lawful (or unlawful) to go to war in the first place.

Principles of jus ad bellum

Proper authority and public declaration

The principle of right authority suggests that a war is just only if waged by a legitimate authority. Such authority is rooted in the notion of state sovereignty.[3] In his Summa Theologica St. Thomas Aquinas notes that to be a just war, war has not only to be declared publicly, but also must be declared by the proper authority.[4]

Proper authority is what differentiates war from murder: "It is the rules of warfare that give the practice meaning, that distinguish war from murder and soldiers from criminals".[5] A soldier is treated as a prisoner of war (POW) and not a criminal because they are operating under the proper authority of the state and cannot be held individually responsible for actions committed under the orders of their military leadership.

Just cause / right intention

According to the principle of right intention, the aim of war must not be to pursue narrowly defined national interests, but rather to re-establish a just peace. This state of peace should be preferable to the conditions that would have prevailed had the war not occurred. Wars cannot be fought simply to annex property or install a regime change. Current doctrines of "anticipatory self-defense" or preemptive strikes, sometimes associated with the Bush Doctrine, have challenged concepts of right intention/just cause. Right cause includes humanitarian intervention, particularly when actions "shock the conscience". The responsibility to protect covers more in depth the nature of humanitarian intervention.

Probability of success

According to this principle, there must be good grounds for concluding that aims of the just war are achievable.[3] This principle emphasizes that mass violence must not be undertaken if it is unlikely to secure the just cause.[6] This criterion is to avoid invasion for invasion's sake and links to the proportionality criteria. One cannot invade if there is no chance of actually winning. However, wars are fought with imperfect knowledge, so one must simply be able to make a logical case that one can win; there is no way to know this in advance. These criteria move the conversation from moral and theoretical grounds to practical grounds.[7] Essentially, this is meant to gather coalition building and win approval of other state actors.

Proportionality

The principle of proportionality stipulates that the violence used in the war must be proportional to the military objectives. This objective is meant to preclude "scorched earth" policies. The level of military victory must be proportional to the level of destruction that ensues. For example, if there is one enemy combatant in a shopping plaza full of 400 civilians, it would not be considered proportional to the blow up the plaza. However, if there is a high value military target in an area with far fewer civilians (a car or a private home) an attack and the collateral damage may be considered justifiable under the rule of proportionality.

Last resort

The principle of last resort stipulates that all non-violent options must first be exhausted before the use of force can be justified. Diplomatic options, sanctions, and other non-military methods must be attempted or validly ruled out before the engagement of hostilities. Further, in regard to the amount of harm—proportionally—the principle of last resort would support using small intervention forces first and then escalating rather than starting a war with massive force such as carpet bombing or nuclear attacks.[8]

History

St. Thomas Aquinas is one of the earliest philosophers on what makes a just war. His list of criteria were intended to protect civilians and guarantee that wars were not just fought for the interest of private parties.[4][9]

After the Peace of Westphalia, which ended the Thirty Years' War, scholars became concerned with finding a way to control interstate war while respecting state sovereignty.[4][10] It wasn’t until the formation of the United Nations after World War II that notions of jus ad bellum were formalized.

The modern era

Since the 1950s, declarations of jus ad bellum have dropped dramatically.[11] In "Why States No Longer Declare War" Tanisha Fazal notes the drop in formal declarations of war since the 1950s.[11] This may be as a result of the nuance of war in modern times, given the rise of non-state actors such as terrorist groups.

gollark: They need to be able to operate independently of the network, or everything will go horribly wrong if they go into a tunnel, or there's a temporary outage.
gollark: Honestly it doesn't seem useful for *that*, either.
gollark: I can see it being used for specialty applications like that, sure, but it does *not* seem useful in a generic router-type device.
gollark: It honestly seems mostly pointless though, given that it doesn't go through walls and apparently works at roughly... cable ranges.
gollark: I've never heard it called WiFi type C, I thought it was just 802.11ad or something.

See also

References

  1. "International Humanitarian Law: Answers to Your Questions". International Committee of the Red Cross. 9 June 2020. Section 2: "What are jus ad bellum and jus in bello?". Retrieved 3 August 2020.
  2. "Charter of the United Nations". Chapter VII: "Action with Respect to Threats to the Peace, Breaches of the Peace and Acts of Aggression". Retrieved 2014-08-22.
  3. Don Hubert and Thomas G. Weiss et al. "The Responsibility to Protect: Supplementary Volume to the Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty". (Canada: International Development Research Centre, 2001)
  4. Rochester, J. Martin (February 19, 2016). The New Warfare: Rethinking Rules for an Unruly World. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-317-27642-5.
  5. Finnemore, M. (1999). "Rules of war and wars of rules: The international red cross and the restraint of state violence". In John Boli and George M. Thomas (ed.). Constructing World Culture: International Nongovernmental Organizations Since 1875. Stanford University Press. pp. 149–165. ISBN 978-0-8047-3422-6.
  6. "War (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". plato.stanford.edu. Retrieved 2014-08-27.
  7. Seybolt, Taylor B. (January 2007). Humanitarian Military Intervention: The Conditions for Success and Failure. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-925243-5.
  8. "Just War Theory and the Last of Last Resort - Ethics & International Affairs". Ethics & International Affairs. 12 June 2015. Retrieved April 2, 2017.
  9. "The Church's Just War Theory - Part 1". www.catholiceducation.org. Retrieved April 2, 2017.
  10. "Peace of Westphalia". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved April 2, 2017.
  11. Fazal, Tanisha M. (2012). "Why States No Longer Declare War". Security Studies. 21 (4): 557–593. doi:10.1080/09636412.2012.734227.
This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.