An Essay Concerning Human Understanding

An Essay Concerning Human Understanding is a work by John Locke concerning the foundation of human knowledge and understanding. It first appeared in 1689 (although dated 1690) with the printed title An Essay Concerning Humane Understanding. He describes the mind at birth as a blank slate (tabula rasa, although he did not use those actual words) filled later through experience. The essay was one of the principal sources of empiricism in modern philosophy, and influenced many enlightenment philosophers, such as David Hume and George Berkeley.

An Essay Concerning Human Understanding
Title page of the first edition
AuthorJohn Locke
CountryEngland
LanguageEnglish
SubjectEpistemology
Publication date
1689
(dated 1690)

Book I of the Essay is Locke's attempt to refute the rationalist notion of innate ideas. Book II sets out Locke's theory of ideas, including his distinction between passively acquired simple ideas, such as "red," "sweet," "round," etc., and actively built complex ideas, such as numbers, causes and effects, abstract ideas, ideas of substances, identity, and diversity. Locke also distinguishes between the truly existing primary qualities of bodies, like shape, motion and the arrangement of minute particles, and the secondary qualities that are "powers to produce various sensations in us"[1] such as "red" and "sweet." These secondary qualities, Locke claims, are dependent on the primary qualities. He also offers a theory of personal identity, offering a largely psychological criterion. Book III is concerned with language, and Book IV with knowledge, including intuition, mathematics, moral philosophy, natural philosophy ("science"), faith, and opinion.

Book I

The main thesis is that there are "No Innate Principles," by reasoning that "if we will attentively consider new born children, we shall have little reason to think that they bring many ideas into the world with them," and that, "by degrees afterward, ideas come into their minds."[2] Book I of the Essay is devoted to an attack on nativism or, the doctrine of innate ideas; Locke indeed sought to rebut a prevalent view of innate ideas that was vehemently held by philosophers of his time. He allowed that some ideas are in the mind from an early age, but argued that such ideas are furnished by the senses starting in the womb; for instance, differences between colours or tastes. If we have a universal understanding of a concept like sweetness, it is not because this is an innate idea, but because we are all exposed to sweet tastes at an early age.[3]

One of Locke's fundamental arguments against innate ideas is the very fact that there is no truth to which all people attest. He took the time to argue against a number of propositions that rationalists offer as universally accepted truth, for instance the principle of identity, pointing out that at the very least children and idiots are often unaware of these propositions.[4] In anticipating a counterargument, namely the use of reason to comprehend already existent innate ideas, Locke states that "by this means there will be no Difference between the Maxims of the Mathematicians, and Theorems they deduce from them: All must equally allow’d innate, they being all Discoveries made by the use of reason."[5]

Book II

Whereas Book I is intended to reject the doctrine of innate ideas proposed by Descartes and the rationalists, Book II explains that every idea is derived from experience either by sensation—i.e. direct sensory information—or reflection—i.e. "the perception of the operations of our own mind within us, as it is employed about the ideas it has got."

In Book II, Locke focuses on the ideas of substances and qualities, in which the former are “an unknown support of qualities” and latter have the “power to produce ideas in our mind.”[6] Substance is what holds qualities together, while qualities themselves allow us to perceive and identify objects. A substance consists of bare particulars and does not have properties in themselves except the ability to support qualities. Substances are “nothing but the assumption of an unknown support for a group of qualities that produce simple ideas in us.”[7] Despite his explanation, the existence of substances is still questionable as they cannot necessarily be “perceived” by themselves and can only be sensed through the qualities.

In terms of qualities, Locke divides such into primary and secondary, whereby the former give our minds ideas based on sensation and actual experience. In contrast, secondary qualities allow our minds to understand something based on reflection, in which we associate what we perceive with other ideas of our own.[8]

Furthermore, Book II is also a systematic argument for the existence of an intelligent being:

Thus, from the consideration of ourselves, and what we infallibly find in our own constitutions, our reason leads us to the knowledge of this certain and evident truth, that there is an eternal, most powerful, and most knowing being; which whether any one will please to call God, it matters not!

Locke contends that consciousness is what distinguishes selves, and thus,[9]

…in this alone consists personal Identity, i.e. the sameness of rational Being: And as far as this consciousness can be extended backwards to any past Action or Thought, so far reaches the Identity of that Person; it is the same self now it was then; and ‘tis by the same self with this present one that now reflects on it, that that Action was done.

Book III

Book III focuses on words. Locke connects words to the ideas they signify, claiming that man is unique in being able to frame sounds into distinct words and to signify ideas by those words, and then that these words are built into language.

Chapter ten in this book focuses on "Abuse of Words." Here, Locke criticizes metaphysicians for making up new words that have no clear meaning. He also criticizes the use of words which are not linked to clear ideas, and to those who change the criteria or meaning underlying a term.

Thus, Locke uses a discussion of language to demonstrate sloppy thinking, following the Port-Royal Logique (1662)[10] in numbering among the abuses of language those that he calls "affected obscurity" in chapter 10. Locke complains that such obscurity is caused by, for example, philosophers who, to confuse their readers, invoke old terms and give them unexpected meanings or who construct new terms without clearly defining their intent. Writers may also invent such obfuscation to make themselves appear more educated or their ideas more complicated and nuanced or erudite than they actually are.

Book IV

This book focuses on knowledge in general—that it can be thought of as the sum of ideas and perceptions. Locke discusses the limit of human knowledge, and whether such can be said to be accurate or truthful.

Thus, there is a distinction between what an individual might claim to know, as part of a system of knowledge, and whether or not that claimed knowledge is actual. Locke writes at the beginning of the fourth chapter ("Of the Reality of Knowledge"):

I doubt not my Reader by this Time may be apt to think that I have been all this while only building a Castle in the Air; and be ready to say to me, To what purpose all of this stir? Knowledge, say you, is only the Perception of the Agreement or Disagreement of our own Ideas: but who knows what those Ideas may be?… But of what use is all this fine Knowledge of Man's own Imaginations, to a Man that enquires after the reality of things? It matters now that Mens Fancies are, 'tis the Knowledge of Things that is only to be priz'd; 'tis this alone gives a Value to our Reasonings, and Preference to one Man's Knowledge over another's, that is of Things as they really are, and of Dreams and Fancies.

In the last chapter of the book, Locke introduces the major classification of sciences into physics, semiotics, and ethics.

Reaction, response, and influence

Many of Locke's views were sharply criticized by rationalists and empiricists alike. In 1704, rationalist Gottfried Leibniz wrote a response to Locke's work in the form of a chapter-by-chapter rebuttal, titled the Nouveaux essais sur l'entendement humain ('New Essays on Human Understanding'). Leibniz was critical of a number of Locke's views in the Essay, including his rejection of innate ideas; his skepticism about species classification; and the possibility that matter might think, among other things. Leibniz thought that Locke's commitment to ideas of reflection in the Essay ultimately made him incapable of escaping the nativist position or being consistent in his empiricist doctrines of the mind's passivity.

Empiricist George Berkeley was equally critical of Locke's views in the Essay. Berkeley's most notable criticisms of Locke were first published in A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, in which Berkeley holds that Locke's conception of abstract ideas are incoherent and lead to severe contradictions. He also argues that Locke's conception of material substance was unintelligible, a view which he also later advanced in the Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous.

At the same time, Locke's work provided crucial groundwork for future empiricists such as David Hume. John Wynne published An Abridgment of Mr. Locke's Essay concerning the Human Understanding, with Locke's approval, in 1696. Likewise, Louisa Capper wrote An Abridgment of Locke's Essay concerning the Human Understanding, published in 1811.

Some European philosophers saw the book's impact on psychology as comparable to Isaac Newton's impact upon science. Voltaire wrote:[11]

Just as a skilled anatomist explains the workings of the human body, so does Locke's Essay on the Human Understanding give the natural history of consciousness.… So many philosophers having written the romance of the soul, a sage has arrived who has modestly written its history.

Chapter break down

Volume I[12]
Chapter Book I — Neither Principles Nor Ideas Are Innate
1 No Innate Speculative Principles
2 No innate Practical Principals
3 Other Considerations Concerning Innate Principals, Both Speculative and Practical
Chapter Book II — Of Ideas
1 Of Ideas in General, and Their Original
2 Of Simple Ideas
3 Of Simple Ideas of Sense
4 Idea of Solidity
5 Of Simple Ideas of Divers Senses
6 Of Simple Ideas of Reflection
7 Of Simple Ideas of Both Sensation and Reflection
8 Some Further Considerations Concerning Our Simple Ideas of Sensation
9 Of Perception
10 Of Retention
11 Of Discerning, and Other Operations of the Mind
12 Of Complex Ideas
13 Complex Ideas of Simple Modes: And First, of the Simple Modes of Idea of Space
14 Idea of Duration and its Simple Modes
15 Ideas of Duration and Expansion, Considered Together
16 Idea of Number
17 Of Infinity
18 Other Simple Modes
19 Of the Modes of Thinking
20 Of Modes of Pleasure and Pain
21 Of Power
22 Of Mixed Modes
23 Of Our Complex Ideas of Substances
24 Of Collective Ideas of Substances
25 Of Relation
26 Of Cause and Effect, and Other Relations
27 Of Identity and Diversity
28 Of Other Relations
29 Of Clear and Obscure, Distinct and Confused Ideas
30 Of Real and Fantastical Ideas
31 Of Adequate and Inadequate Ideas
32 Of True and False Ideas
33 Of the Association of Ideas

Editions

  • Locke, John. 1690. An Essay Concerning Humane Understanding (1st ed.). 1 vols. London: Thomas Basset.
  • — 1894. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, edited by Alexander Campbell Fraser. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • — 1722. Works, Vol 1. London: Taylor.
gollark: umnikos
gollark: !hwdyk msg
gollark: Pyrotelekinetic
gollark: !hwdyk msg
gollark: LyricLy

See also

  • Second Treatise on Civil Government

References

  1. Essay, II, viii, 10
  2. Essay, I, iii, 2.
  3. Essay, I, ii, 15.
  4. Essay, I, iv, 3.
  5. Locke, John (1753). An Essay concerning Human Understanding ... The fourteenth edition. [With a portrait.]. S. Birt.
  6. Locke, John. "An Essay Concerning Human Understanding Book II: Ideas" (PDF). Early Modern Texts. Jonathan Bennett. Retrieved 22 May 2019.
  7. Kemerling, Garth. "Complex Ideas". A guide to Locke's Essays. Creative Commons. Retrieved 22 May 2019.
  8. Kemerling, Garth. "Locke: The Origin of Ideas". A guide to Locke's Essays. Creative Commons. Retrieved 22 May 2019.
  9. Gordon-Roth, 2020
  10. Arnauld, Antoine, and Pierre Nicole. 1662. "Observations importantes touchant la définition des noms." Ch. 13 in La logique ou l'Art de penser, part 1. Paris: Jean Guignart, Charles Savreux, & Jean de Lavnay.
  11. Gillispie, Charles Coulston (1960). The Edge of Objectivity: An Essay in the History of Scientific Ideas. Princeton University Press. p. 159. ISBN 0-691-02350-6.
  12. Locke, John [1690] (2017). An Essay Concerning Humane Understanding, Volume I at Project Gutenberg

Bibliography

This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.