Löwenheim number

In mathematical logic the Löwenheim number of an abstract logic is the smallest cardinal number for which a weak downward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem holds.[1] They are named after Leopold Löwenheim, who proved that these exist for a very broad class of logics.

Abstract logic

An abstract logic, for the purpose of Löwenheim numbers, consists of:

  • A collection of "sentences";
  • A collection of "models", each of which is assigned a cardinality;
  • A relation between sentences and models that says that a certain sentence is "satisfied" by a particular model.

The theorem does not require any particular properties of the sentences or models, or of the satisfaction relation, and they may not be the same as in ordinary first-order logic. It thus applies to a very broad collection of logics, including first-order logic, higher-order logics, and infinitary logics.

Definition

The Löwenheim number of a logic L is the smallest cardinal κ such that if an arbitrary sentence of L has any model, the sentence has a model of cardinality no larger than κ.

Löwenheim proved the existence of this cardinal for any logic in which the collection of sentences forms a set, using the following argument. Given such a logic, for each sentence φ, let κφ be the smallest cardinality of a model of φ, if φ has any model, and let κφ be 0 otherwise. Then the set of cardinals

{ κφ : φ is a sentence in L }

exists by the axiom of replacement. The supremum of this set, by construction, is the Löwenheim number of L. This argument is non-constructive: it proves the existence of the Löwenheim number, but does not provide an immediate way to calculate it.

Extensions

Two extensions of the definition have been considered:[2]

  • The LöwenheimSkolem number of an abstract logic L is the smallest cardinal κ such that if any set of sentences T L has a model then it has a model of size no larger than max(|T|, κ).
  • The LöwenheimSkolemTarski number of L is the smallest cardinal such that if A is any structure for L there is an elementary substructure of A of size no more than κ. This requires that the logic have a suitable notion of "elementary substructure", for example by using the normal definition of a "structure" from predicate logic.

For any logic for which the numbers exist, the LöwenheimSkolemTarski number will be no less than the LöwenheimSkolem number, which in turn will be no less than the Löwenheim number.

Examples

  • The Löwenheim–Skolem theorem shows that the LöwenheimSkolemTarski number of first-order logic is 0. This means, in particular, that if a sentence of first-order logic is satisfiable, then the sentence is satisfiable in a countable model.
  • It is known that the LöwenheimSkolem number of second-order logic is larger than the first measurable cardinal, if there is a measurable cardinal.[3] (And the same holds for its Hanf number.) The Löwenheim number of the universal (fragment of) second-order logic however is less than the first supercompact cardinal (assuming it exists).

Notes

  1. Zhang 2002 page 77
  2. Magidor and Väänänen 2009/2010
  3. Magidor and Väänänen 2009/2010.
gollark: It has arbitrary code execution, reminders, Wikipedia lookups, simulated telephony, IRC bridging, DuckDuckGo, data, and deletion.
gollark: You should add my bot instead. It's better.
gollark: I wonder if I can make a bot automatically create several hundred threads.
gollark: https://i.imgur.com/IbUYqrL.jpeg
gollark: Wow, what a real repost which utterly exists. Good job.

References

  • Menachem Magidor and Jouko Väänänen. "On Löwenheim-Skolem-Tarski numbers for extensions of first order logic", Report No. 15 (2009/2010) of the Mittag-Leffler Institute.
  • Yi Zhang Logic and algebra 2002. ISBN 0-8218-2984-X
This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.