Diaconescu's theorem

In mathematical logic, Diaconescu's theorem, or the Goodman–Myhill theorem, states that the full axiom of choice is sufficient to derive the law of the excluded middle, or restricted forms of it, in constructive set theory. It was discovered in 1975 by Diaconescu[1] and later by Goodman and Myhill.[2] Already in 1967, Errett Bishop posed the Theorem as an exercise (Problem 2 on page 58 in Foundations of constructive analysis[3]).

Proof

For any proposition , we can build the sets

and

These are sets, using the axiom of specification. In classical set theory this would be equivalent to

and similarly for . However, without the law of the excluded middle, these equivalences cannot be proven; in fact the two sets are not even provably finite (in the usual sense of being in bijection with a natural number, though they would be in the Dedekind sense).

Assuming the axiom of choice, there exists a choice function for the set ; that is, a function such that

By the definition of the two sets, this means that

,

which implies

But since (by the axiom of extensionality), therefore , so

Thus As this could be done for any proposition, this completes the proof that the axiom of choice implies the law of the excluded middle.

The proof relies on the use of the full separation axiom. In constructive set theories with only the predicative separation, the form of P will be restricted to sentences with bound quantifiers only, giving only a restricted form of the law of the excluded middle. This restricted form is still not acceptable constructively.

In constructive type theory, or in Heyting arithmetic extended with finite types, there is typically no separation at all - subsets of a type are given different treatments. A form of the axiom of choice is a theorem, yet excluded middle is not.

Notes

  1. R. Diaconescu, "Axiom of choice and complementation", Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society 51:176-178 (1975)
  2. N. D. Goodman and J. Myhill, “Choice Implies Excluded Middle”, Zeitschrift fur Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 24:461 (1978)
  3. E. Bishop, Foundations of constructive analysis, McGraw-Hill (1967)
gollark: No, we did that ages ago, it's in the company handbook.
gollark: Our containment octahedra can protect them from this actually.
gollark: It's not like we haven't had access to the platonic realm of forms since 2007.
gollark: If they were, they would already retroactively have been.
gollark: (it has funcsave anyway, which is perfect and without flaw)
This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.