Complete partial order

In mathematics, the phrase complete partial order is variously used to refer to at least three similar, but distinct, classes of partially ordered sets, characterized by particular completeness properties. Complete partial orders play a central role in theoretical computer science: in denotational semantics and domain theory.

Definitions

A complete partial order abbreviated cpo can, depending on context, refer to any of the following concepts.

  • A partially ordered set is a directed-complete partial order (dcpo) if each of its directed subsets has a supremum. A subset of a partial order is directed if it is non-empty and every pair of elements has an upper bound in the subset. In the literature, dcpos sometimes also appear under the label up-complete poset.
  • A partially ordered set is a pointed directed-complete partial order if it is a dcpo with a least element. They are sometimes abbreviated cppos.
  • A partially ordered set is a ω-complete partial order (ω-cpo) if it is a poset in which every ω-chain (x1x2x3x4≤...) has a supremum that belongs to the underlying set of the poset. Every dcpo is an ω-cpo, since every ω-chain is a directed set, but the converse is not true. However, every ω-cpo with a basis is also a dcpo (with the same basis).[1] An ω-cpo (dcpo) with a basis is also called a continuous ω-cpo (continuous dcpo).

Note that complete partial order is never used to mean a poset in which all subsets have suprema; the terminology complete lattice is used for this concept.

Requiring the existence of directed suprema can be motivated by viewing directed sets as generalized approximation sequences and suprema as limits of the respective (approximative) computations. This intuition, in the context of denotational semantics, was the motivation behind the development of domain theory.

The dual notion of a directed complete poset is called a filtered complete partial order. However, this concept occurs far less frequently in practice, since one usually can work on the dual order explicitly.

Examples

  • Every finite poset is directed complete.
  • All complete lattices are also directed complete.
  • For any poset, the set of all non-empty filters, ordered by subset inclusion, is a dcpo. Together with the empty filter it is also pointed. If the order has binary meets, then this construction (including the empty filter) actually yields a complete lattice.
  • The set of all partial functions on some given set S can be ordered by defining f  g for functions f and g if and only if g extends f, i.e. if the domain of f is a subset of the domain of g and the values of f and g agree on all inputs for which both functions are defined. (Equivalently, f  g if and only if f  g where f and g are identified with their respective graphs.) This order is a pointed dcpo, where the least element is the nowhere-defined function (with empty domain). In fact, ≤ is also bounded complete. This example also demonstrates why it is not always natural to have a greatest element.
  • The specialization order of any sober space is a dcpo.
  • Let us use the term “deductive system” as a set of sentences closed under consequence (for defining notion of consequence, let us use e.g. Alfred Tarski's algebraic approach[2][3]). There are interesting theorems that concern a set of deductive systems being a directed-complete partial ordering.[4] Also, a set of deductive systems can be chosen to have a least element in a natural way (so that it can be also a pointed dcpo), because the set of all consequences of the empty set (i.e. “the set of the logically provable / logically valid sentences”) is (1) a deductive system (2) contained by all deductive systems.

Properties

An ordered set P is a pointed dcpo if and only if every chain has a supremum in P, i.e., P is chain-complete[5]. Alternatively, an ordered set P is a pointed dcpo if and only if every order-preserving self-map of P has a least fixpoint. Every set S can be turned into a pointed dcpo by adding a least element ⊥ and introducing a flat order with ⊥  s and s  s for every s  S and no other order relations.

Continuous functions and fixpoints

A function f between two dcpos P and Q is called (Scott) continuous if it maps directed sets to directed sets while preserving their suprema:

  • is directed for every directed .
  • for every directed .

Note that every continuous function between dcpos is a monotone function. This notion of continuity is equivalent to the topological continuity induced by the Scott topology.

The set of all continuous functions between two dcpos P and Q is denoted [P  Q]. Equipped with the pointwise order, this is again a dcpo, and a cpo whenever Q is a cpo. Thus the complete partial orders with Scott-continuous maps form a cartesian closed category.[6]

Every order-preserving self-map f of a cpo (P, ⊥) has a least fixpoint.[7] If f is continuous then this fixpoint is equal to the supremum of the iterates (⊥, f(⊥), f(f(⊥)), … fn(⊥), …) of ⊥ (see also the Kleene fixpoint theorem).

gollark: They've had to add extra power connectors to PSUs now.
gollark: The highest end consumes ridiculous amounts of power now. Particularly the Hopper ones/4000 series.
gollark: Apparently, the COVID-19 years messed with some people's perception of time.
gollark: As planned.
gollark: This sounds like a <@488810726803243021> thing.

See also

Directed completeness relates in various ways to other completeness notions such as chain completeness. Directed completeness alone is quite a basic property that occurs often in other order-theoretic investigations, using for instance algebraic posets and the Scott topology.

Notes

  1. Abramsky S, Gabbay DM, Maibaum TS (1994). Handbook of Logic in Computer Science, volume 3. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Prop 2.2.14, pp. 20. ISBN 9780198537625.
  2. Tarski, Alfred: Bizonyítás és igazság / Válogatott tanulmányok. Gondolat, Budapest, 1990. (Title means: Proof and truth / Selected papers.)
  3. Stanley N. Burris and H.P. Sankappanavar: A Course in Universal Algebra
  4. See online in p. 24 exercises 5–6 of §5 in BurSan:UnivAlg. Or, on paper, see Tar:BizIg.
  5. Markowsky, George (1976), "Chain-complete posets and directed sets with applications", Algebra Universalis, 6 (1): 53–68, doi:10.1007/bf02485815, MR 0398913.
  6. Barendregt, Henk, The lambda calculus, its syntax and semantics Archived 2004-08-23 at the Wayback Machine, North-Holland (1984)
  7. See Knaster–Tarski theorem; The foundations of program verification, 2nd edition, Jacques Loeckx and Kurt Sieber, John Wiley & Sons, ISBN 0-471-91282-4, Chapter 4; the Knaster–Tarski theorem, formulated over cpo's, is given to prove as exercise 4.3-5 on page 90.

References

  • Davey, B.A.; Priestley, H. A. (2002). Introduction to Lattices and Order (Second ed.). Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-78451-4.
This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.