Charles Renouvier

Charles Bernard Renouvier (French: [ʁənuvje]; January 1, 1815 – September 1, 1903) was a French philosopher. He considered himself a "Swedenborg of history" who sought to update the philosophy of Kantian liberalism and individualism for the socio-economic realities of the late nineteenth century, and influenced the sociological method of Émile Durkheim.[3][4][5]

Charles Renouvier
Born(1815-01-01)January 1, 1815
DiedSeptember 1, 1903(1903-09-01) (aged 88)
Alma materÉcole Polytechnique
Era19th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolCritical philosophy[2]
Main interests
Metaphysics
Notable ideas
Néo-criticisme, uchronia

Biography

Renouvier was born in Montpellier and educated in Paris at the École Polytechnique. He took an early interest in politics, but never held public office, spending his time writing, away from public scrutiny.

Philosophy

Renouvier was the first French philosopher after Nicolas Malebranche to formulate a complete idealistic system, and had a vast influence on the development of French thought. His system is based on Immanuel Kant's,[6] as his chosen term "néo-criticisme" indicates; but it is a transformation rather than a continuation of Kantianism.

The two leading ideas are the dislike of the "unknowable" in all its forms, and a reliance on the validity of personal experience. The former accounts for Renouvier's acceptance of Kant's phenomenalism, combined with rejection of the thing-in-itself. It accounts, too, for his polemic on the one hand against a Substantial Soul, a Buddhistic Absolute, an Infinite Spiritual Substance; on the other hand against the no less mysterious material or dynamic substratum by which naturalistic Monism explains the world. He maintains that nothing exists except presentations, which are not merely sensational, and have an objective aspect no less than a subjective. To explain the formal organization of our experience, Renouvier adopts a modified version of the Kantian categories.

The insistence on the validity of personal experience leads Renouvier to a yet more important divergence from Kant in his treatment of volition. Liberty, he says, in a much wider sense than Kant, is man's fundamental characteristic. Human freedom acts in the phenomenal, not in an imaginary noumenal sphere. Belief is not merely intellectual, but is determined by an act of will affirming what we hold to be morally good.

In his religious views, Renouvier makes a considerable approximation to Gottfried Leibniz. He holds that we are rationally justified in affirming human immortality and the existence of a finite God who is to be a constitutional ruler, but not a despot, over the souls of people. He nevertheless regards atheism as preferable to a belief in an infinite Deity.

Renouvier's dislike of the unknowable also led him to take up arms against the notion of an actual infinite. He believed that an infinite sum must be a name for something incomplete. If one begins to count, "one, two, three ..." there never comes a time when one is entitled to shout "infinity"! Infinity is a project, never a fact, in the neocritical view.

Renouvier became an important influence upon the thought of American psychologist and philosopher William James. James wrote that "but for the decisive impression made on me in the 1870s by his masterly advocacy of pluralism, I might never have got free from the monistic superstition under which I had grown up."

Works

  • Essais de critique générale (1854–64)
  • Science de la morale[7] (1869)
  • Uchronie (1876)
  • Comment je suis arrivé à cette conclusion (1885)
  • Esquisse d'une classification systématique des doctrines philosophiques (1885–86)
  • Philosophie analytique de l'histoire (1896–97)
  • La Nouvelle Monadologie (1899)
  • Histoire et solution des problèmes métaphysiques (1901)
  • Victor Hugo: Le Poète (1893)
  • Victor Hugo: Le Philosophe (1900)
  • Les Dilemmes de la métaphysique pure[7] (1901)
  • Le Personnalisme (1903)
  • Critique de la doctrine de Kant[7] (1906)
gollark: Spirit is very knowledgeable, but will also ruthlessly correct any mistake anyone makes.
gollark: OH NOYOU PINGED HIM
gollark: If you want illumination inside or something, it would probably be cheaper to just get really bright LEDs.
gollark: I hope this doesn't end up in some sort of dystopian future where laser diodes and other interesting components are only available within highly integrated and expensive/hard to modify systems.
gollark: It's some expensive thing which absorbs most light.

See also

Notes

  1. "Herbert Spencer et Charles Renouvier"
  2. John I. Brooks, The Eclectic Legacy: Academic Philosophy and the Human Sciences in Nineteenth-century France, University of Delaware Press, 1998, p. 150.
  3. Geenens, Raf; Rosenblatt, Helena (2012). French Liberalism from Montesquieu to the Present Day. Cambridge University Press. p. 239.
  4. Ferguson, Niall (2008). Virtual History: Alternatives And Counterfactuals. Basic Books. p. 9.
  5. Jones, Robert Alun (2005). The Secret of the Totem: Religion and Society from McLennan to Freud. Columbia University Press.
  6. Kant, Philosophy of, The Catholic Encyclopedia
  7. "Textes philosophiques complets". at www.ac-nancy-metz.fr. Archived from the original on December 4, 2004.

Further reading

  • Emmanuel Carrère: Le Détroit de Behring. P.O.L., Paris 1986.
  • Paul K. Alkon: Origins of Futuristic Fiction. University of Georgia Press, 1987.
  • Bernard J. Looks: How I Arrived At This Conclusion: A Philosophical Memoir. Translation to English of Renouvier's Comment je suis arrivé à cette conclusion. YBK Publishers, 2011.
This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.